Abstract: The concept of quantum information introduced by quantum
mechanics serves to describe uniformly future and past and thus the present as
the frontier of time. If one uses the notion of “length of now” defined as the
period of the de Broglie wave associable to any physical item, the “length of
now” of the apparatus can be visualized as a random chosen point onto the
segment of the “length of now” of the measured quantum entity. Thus quantum
mechanics is forced to describe uniformly the future, present and past of the
investigated system. The future is represented as a coherent whole, the present
as a choice among infinitely many alternatives, and past as a well-ordering
obtained as a result of a series of choices. The concept of quantum information
unifies the future, present, and past as a measurable physical quantity. It
describes the frontier of time, that “now”, which transforms future into past.
The quantity of quantum information can be interpreted as the transfinite
generalization of information. Its units, the quantum bits (qubits) are
correspondingly the generalization of the units of classical information, the
bits. A qubit is an elementary choice among a continuum of alternatives.
The thesis is: The concept of quantum information introduced by quantum mechanics serves to describe uniformly future and past and thus the present as the frontier of time.
The thesis is: The concept of quantum information introduced by quantum mechanics serves to describe uniformly future and past and thus the present as the frontier of time.
Preliminary notes: The conception of quantum information was introduced in the theory of quantum information
studying the phenomena of entanglement in quantum mechanics. The entanglement was theoretically forecast in the
famous papers of Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen (1935) and independently by Shrödinger (1935) deducing it from
Hilbert space, the basic mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics. However, the former three demonstrated the
forecast phenomenon as the proof of the alleged “incompleteness of quantum mechanics”. John Bell (1964) deduced
a sufficient condition as an experimentally verifiable criterion in order to distinguish classical from quantum
correlation (entanglement). Aspect, Grangier, and Roger (1981, 1982) confirmed experimentally the existence of
quantum correlations exceeding the upper limit of the possible classical correlations. The theory of quantum
information has thrived since the end of the last century in the areas of quantum computer, quantum communication,
and quantum cryptography.
The fundament of quantum information is the concept of ‘quantum bit’, “qubit” definable as the normed
superposition of any two orthogonal subspaces of complex Hilbert space as follows:
‘Qubit’ is: 𝛼|0⟩+𝛽|1⟩ where 𝛼, 𝛽 are complex numbers such that |𝛼|2+ |𝛽|2=1, and |0⟩, |1⟩ are any two orthonormal
vectors (e.g. the orthonormal bases of any two subspaces) in any vector space (e.g. Hilbert space, Euclidean space,
etc.). Thus Hilbert space underlying quantum mechanics is representable as the quantity of quantum information and
any wave function, i.e. any state of any quantum system being a point in it can be seen as a value of that quantity.
Consequently all physical processes turn out to be quantum-informational, and nature or the universe is a quantum
computer processing quantum information.
The qubit is also isomorphic to a ball in Euclidean space, in which two points are chosen: A qubit is equivalently
representable as a unit ball in Euclidean space and two points, the one chosen within the ball, and the other being the
orthogonal projection on its surface, i.e. as a mapping of a unit ball onto its surface (or any other unit sphere).
Quantum information can be interpreted as the transfinite generalization of information. Its unit,
a qubit, can be interpreted as a choice among an infinite set of alternatives. It generalizes the unit of classical
information, a bit, which refer to a finite set of alternatives.
If one uses the notion of “length of now” defined as the period of the de Broglie (1925) wave associable to any
physical item, the “length of now” of the apparatus can be visualized as a random chosen point onto the segment of
the “length of now” of the measured quantum entity. Thus quantum mechanics is forced to describe uniformly the
future, present and past of the investigated system. Future is represented as a coherent whole, present as a choice
among infinitely many alternatives, and past as a well-ordering obtained as a result of a series of choices. The
concept of quantum information unifies the future, present, and past as a measurable physical quantity. It describes
the frontier of time, that “now”, which transforms future into past.
The theorems about the absence of hidden variables in quantum mechanics (Neumann 1932; Kochen, Specker 1968)
demonstrate that the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics implies that no well-ordering of any coherent
state might exist before measurement. However, the same coherent state is transformed into a well-ordered series of
results in time after measurement. In order to be equated the state before and after measurement, the well-ordering
theorem equivalent to the axiom of choice is necessary. The measurement mediating between them should be
interpreted as an absolutely random choice of an element of the coherent state, for which no constructive way
(equivalent to some “hidden variable”) can exist in principle. The quantity of quantum information can describe
uniformly the state before and after measurement (equivalent to a choice among an infinite set). Any wave function,
being a given value of quantum information, “bounds” an unorderable and a well-ordered state as the quantity of
qubits (i.e. the “infinite choices”) necessary for the latter to be obtained from the former.
The quantity of quantum information is also the ordinal corresponding to the infinity series of finite choices. Both
definitions of ‘ordinal’ (Cantor 1897; Neumann 1923) are applicable as the ordinals are small. The ordinal defined in
Cantor – Russell (Russell, Whitehead any edition) generates a statistical ensemble while that in Neumann, a wellordering.
Both correspond one-to-one to a coherent state as the one and same quantity of quantum information
containing in it.
References:
Aspect, A., Grangier, R., Roger, G. (1981) “Experimental Tests of Realistic Local Theories via Bell’s Theorem”,
Physical Review Letters, 47(7): 460-463.
Aspect, A., Grangier, R., Roger, G. (1982) “Experimental Realization of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm Gedanken
Experiment: A New Violation of Bell’s Inequalities”, Physical Review Letters, 49(2): 91-94.
Bell, J. (1964) “On the Einstein ‒ Podolsky ‒ Rosen paradox”, Physics (New York), 1(3): 195-200.
Broglie, L. de (1925) Recherches sur la théorie des quanta (Researches on the quantum theory), Thesis (Paris), 1924.
Annales de Physique (Paris, 10-ème série) 3, 22-128.
Cantor, G. (1897) “Beitrage zur Begrundung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (Zweiter Artikel)”, Mathematische
Annalen, 49(2): 207-246.
Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., Rosen, N. (1935) “Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be
Considered Complete?” Physical Review, 47(10): 777-780.
Kochen, S., Specker, E. (1968) “The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics”, Journal of Mathematics
and Mechanics, 17(1): 59-87.
Neumann, J. von (1923) "Zur Einführung der trasfiniten Zahlen", Acta litterarum ac scientiarum Ragiae Universitatis
Hungaricae Francisco-Josephinae, Sectio scientiarum mathematicarum, 1(4): 199–208.
Neumann, J. von (1932). Mathematical foundation of quantum mechanics [Mathematische Grundlagen der
Quantenmechanik, Berlin: Springer, pp. 167-173 (Chapter IV.2).
Russell, B, Whitehead, A. N. (any edition) Principia Mathematica, Vol. 2(*153), Vol. 3(*251).
Schrödinger, E (1935) “Die gegenwärtige situation in der Quantenmechanik”,
Die aturwissenschaften, 23(48), 807-
812; 23(49), 823-828, 23(50), 844-849.The above text as a PDF or as a video
No comments:
Post a Comment